Jacques Maritain’s "Democratic Faith": Heretical or
Orthodox?
By Thaddeus J. Kozinski
Catholic University of America
In 1864 the ultramontane English Catholic, William George Ward,
described the spiritual dangers that English Roman Catholics faced from
the "national spirit" of their homeland. He writes:
In every nation there is a certain subtle, yet most powerful
influence, which we call the national spirit; it is produced partly by
national character and partly by long-continued habits of legislation
and administration; and it imbues unconsciously the mind of each
individual citizen with an indefinite number of notions, regarded by him
as self-evident first principles, and as beyond the province of
criticism or examination. In like manner, on the Church’s side, there is
a Catholic spirit, and there are Catholic instincts, produced partly by
the working of Catholic truth on those pious and simple souls who
faithfully receive it, and partly by the more direct agency of the
Ecclesia Docens; and this circumambient Catholic atmosphere is
one of her principal instruments in bringing home to each individual the
great truths with which she is entrusted. But these two spirits—the
Catholic and the national respectively—are very far more antagonistic
than harmonious. To the former we cannot resign ourselves too
unreservedly, for it is the very effluence of God the Holy Ghost.
Towards the prevailing national spirit, on the contrary, our only
reasonable attitude is one of deep jealously and suspicion; because it
is charged with principles which, for the corruption of human nature,
are sure to be more false than true, and from which we should keep
ourselves entirely free, until we have measured them by their only true
standard, the Church’s voice."
In 1951, Jacques Maritain, the neo-Thomist French Catholic, said this
about his first encounter with the "national spirit" of
America:
When he who, meeting for the first time either France or America,
falls in love at first sight, it is because he is confronted with a
moral personality, a moral vocation, something of invaluable dignity,
which is spiritual in nature, and which, I think, in the last analysis
is quickened, in one way or another, by some spark of the Christian
spirit and legacy.
I contrast the attitudes of these men, both brilliant, thoroughly
Orthodox Roman Catholics, because they constitute the attitudinal
antipodes within which American Roman Catholics have historically been
disposed toward the Anglo-American "national spirit" of their
homeland: "deep jealously and suspicion," on the one hand, and
"love at first sight" on the other. A pressing issue that
confronts Catholics in America today, when our culture seems less and
less "quickened by some spark of the Christian spirit and
legacy," is the proper attitude we should have towards the
contemporary effluence of our national spirit. No one could have ever
predicted, not even someone with the prophetic brilliance of Jacques
Maritain, that only two decades after the end of World War II the soul
of America would have been inhabited by spirits so evil that none other
than the vicar of Christ would refer to her as "the culture of
death." Should we, then, adopt the optimistic, 1950’s idealism of
Maritain, seeing an essential compatibility of even today’s American
national spirit with the Holy Spirit? Or should we adopt Ward’s more
somber view, in which "our only reasonable attitude is one of deep
jealously and suspicion"?
In this essay I will attempt my own "discernment of
spirits" to show that the wiser attitude for us to cultivate today
is Ward’s, because Maritain’s overall assessment of the spirit of the
American regime was flawed. To accomplish this I will conduct an
extensive analysis and critique of his famous political concept,
"the democratic charter." The doctrine of the democratic
charter, in a word, states that unity in the truth is not necessarily a
prerequisite for unity in the good. This notion, I shall argue, is
wrong. However, even if I can not show this adequately, accepting the
possibility that theoretically and practically Maritain’s program is
justifiable in itself, it is no longer applicable for "the ethical
and political predicaments facing America and the world today" (in
the words of this conference’s invitation flyer). The possibility of the
sort of consensus Maritain envisioned, one requiring angelic
dispositions without the worship of the King of Angels, is next to zero
in our now thoroughly de-christianized culture of death.
I. Maritain’s Vision for America: A Long Awaited Political
Pentecost
Maritain developed his vision of a Thomistically inspired social and
political philosophy for the modern world during the horrific years of
World War Two. There was a definite sense among Catholics in
Europe and America after the War that the defeat of the anti-Christian
ideologies of Nazism and Fascism would induce a rebirth of a
Christ-based politics in Europe and America. Through his writings and
political action (as the French Ambassador to the UN and a main
architect for the U.N. Declaration on Human Rights) Maritain sought to
sow, both in theory and in practice, the seed for this rebirth. One can
discern in Maritain’s writings an assumption that there existed a sharp
awareness in the minds of Western Europeans of the need for a new
political order based upon a common core of "democratic
values." The horrors of Nazism, fascism and communism should be
attributed to the abandonment of the Gospel as the foundation for
society, and, as Maritain saw things, the reacceptance of the Gospel by
contemporary men would manifest itself in the establishment of a social
and political order rooted in what he called a "personalist
democracy."
This personalist democracy would be nothing less than the
culmination, the ripe societal fruit of the seed of the Gospel planted
nearly two-thousand years ago in the city of Bethlehem. The progressive
American president, Woodrow Wilson, had in a previous era evinced
similar sentiments to Maritain, asking Congress in 1917 to declare war
to defeat the Germans in order to "make the world safe for
democracy," the implied assumption being that democracy was now the
foremost social desideratum of the peoples of the West (whether they
knew it explicitly yet or not). For Maritain, liberal democracy was
indeed such a desideratum, for it represented the progress of man’s
moral consciousness and a "coming of age" of the temporal
order since the Middle Ages. The temporal order had progressed insofar
as it had become more differentiated from the spiritual sphere and more
conscious of its own relative autonomy, distinctness, and dignity, and
morality had evolved insofar as it now recognized the tremendous dignity
of the human person and the priority of freedom.
In proportion as the civil society, or the body politic, has become
more perfectly distinguished from the spiritual realm of the Church—a
process which was in itself but a development of the gospel distinction
between the things that are Caesar’s and the things that are of
God’s—the civil society has become grounded on a common good and a
common task which are of an earthly, "temporal, or
"secular" order, and in which citizens belonging to diverse
spiritual lineages share equally.
For Maritain, the democratic faith was the primary temporal analogue
to the spiritual faith of Christianity, and its inception in the modern
era was valid proof of a genuine moral progression since the Middle
Ages: the democratic faith was a long-awaited political Pentecost.
Now, what was not in any way a development of the Gospel, of
course, was the tragic religious divisions among men and the widespread
apostasy from the Christina Faith. The unity of Faith was, for Maritain,
infinitely superior to any other unity, as it was a unity forged in the
highest things, and in no way could it ever be said, regardless of the
development in the temporal order that may have accompanied it, that
such religious division was anything but an absolute evil. Nevertheless,
for Maritain, it was an inescapable reality permitted by God out of
which has arisen a great good: a new kind of unity—based upon a new
creed—the "creed of freedom":
For a society of free men implies tenets which are at the core of its
very existence. A genuine democracy implies a fundamental agreement
between minds and wills on the bases of life in common; it is aware of
itself and of its principles, and it must be capable of defending and
promoting its own conception of social and political life; it must
bear within itself a common human creed, the creed of
freedom.
Now, to the ears of a Catholic imbued with the Church’s social
teachings, especially since Rerum Novarum, it would seem
that God has given His divine stamp of approval to Maritain’s insights.
We know that Pope Paul VI was a loyal student of Maritain’s thought, and
since Vatican II, the Church has been echoing many of Maritain’s ideas
in her Magisterial teachings: freedom and the dignity of the human
person as the main criteria for the evaluation of any social order
(Dignitatis Humane), the real distinctness, autonomy, and
goodness of the created world (Gaudiam et Spes), and the ethical
superiority of free, democratic political and economic institutions over
centrally planned ones (Centessimus Annus). Nevertheless, not
everything that Maritain taught on social and political matters was
adopted by the Church.
We have already discussed Maritain’s idea of "the democratic
faith"; we now turn to the question of its attainment. Maritain
writes:
Thus it is that men possessing quite different, even
opposite metaphysical or religious outlooks, can converge, not by virtue
of any identity of doctrine, but by virtue of an analogical similitude
in practical principles, toward the same practical conclusions, and can
share in the same practical secular faith, provided that they similarly
revere, perhaps for quite diverse reasons, truth and intelligence, human
dignity, freedom, brotherly love, and the absolute value of moral
good.
Now, it is not manifestly problematic to cite natural and secular
values and goods as primary desirables to which men in the political
arena could devote their hearts and for the accomplishment of which they
could work in the sphere of public life. The problematic aspect is the
idea that the democratic charter, the locus of political unity
constituting the precise good of the temporal order, would be attainable
by men whose theoretical conceptions of and religious beliefs about man,
the world, and God might be totally diverse—and even entirely
erroneous—and whose souls did not have to be sanctified by
supernatural grace.
II. The Democratic Faith: Heretical or Orthodox?
Maritain assumed that there was enough residual intellectual agreement
among American men in the 1950s, in spite of their religious and
philosophical differences, to "undertake a great work."
Apparently he thought widespread agreement about practical goods was
inevitable after the communally-experienced horrors of World War II; the
concerted effort to eradicate commonly-accepted evils like Fascism and
Nazism would clearly reveal to the whole world commonly-accepted goods.
One of these revealed goods, Maritain thought, was the inherent dignity
of the human person, and he thought it sufficient for the cause of world
peace that the West had simply come to a vivid awareness of this good,
even though the theoretical justification of this awareness may have
left something to be desired. Was he correct?
Alasdair MacIntyre, a noted critic of Maritain, sums up the main
problem with the attempt to build a practical consensus in abstraction
from philosophical theory:
What Maritain wished to affirm was a modern version of
Aquinas’ thesis that every human being has within him or herself a
natural knowledge of divine law and hence of what every human being owes
to every other human being. The plain prephilosophical person is always
a person of sufficient moral capacities. But what Maritain failed to
reckon with adequately was the fact that in many cultures and notably in
that of modernity plain persons are misled into giving moral expression
to those capacities through assent to false philosophical theories. So
it has been since the eighteenth century with assent to a conception of
rights alien to and absent from Aquinas’ thought.
According to MacIntyre, Maritain’s democratic charter does not
sufficiently account for the fact that, while men may assent to
practical goods without conscious deference to an abstract philosophical
theory, they, nevertheless, possesses philosophical commitments which
influence and condition the nature and interpretation of that assent,
thereby determining the style of behavior that flows from that assent.
As MacIntyre has shown, rationality itself is a "practice"
that takes its shape in a particular, lived-tradition of rationality,
informed by religious, philosophical, anthropological, epistemological
commitments that in turn inform the precise manner in which that
rationality is practiced by the individuals habituated into a particular
tradition. For MacIntyre, then, the post-World-War II consensus on the
goods constituting the democratic charter was not really a consensus at
all, even though the consenters evinced a common lexicon of "human
rights" and "democratic values"; for, it was built on
sand, on entirely disparate understandings of that lexicon in virtue of
their disparate traditions of rationality: Thomist, Humean, Kantian,
Rousseauian, Nietzchean, Deweyean, etc.. But even if all the consenters
had indeed been rooted in the same tradition (perhaps as the children of
a dysfunctional Enlightenment family!), it was not rooted in that one
tradition of rationality without which, Maritain insisted, the
particular goods of the democratic order would have never even been
recognized, let alone become attainable, the scholastic tradition of
Christian rationality.
Maritain also insisted, however, that even though scholastic thought
was the only philosophical tradition that could coherently ground the
democratic charter in theory—because both the charter and
scholasticism were worldly branches of the same spiritual tree, as it
were, the tree of the Gospel—it was not necessary for modern men to
be grafted onto that tree, that is, to be scholastic or even to profess
Christian belief, in order to give a full and intelligible assent to it.
Why? because the fundamental insight upon which the charter would be
built, the dignity of the human person, was an insight now commonly held
by even a scholastic-and-Gospel-eschewing modern man. As long as this
insight about the dignity of persons remained firmly in the communal
consciousness, as he believed it would because of the evident evolution
of moral consciousness, the democratic charter would work, regardless of
the truth or falsity of the philosophical or religious theories that
served to ground it in the minds of individual men.
In the last fifty years, however, the underpinnings of that
consensus have become unglued. We have also seen a concomitant rise in
the number of false philosophical theories, theories that would
eventually redefine human persons in the same way as the
"undemocratic" Nazis did in order to justify the murder of the
unborn, all under the banner of the "freedom" and
"rights" afforded by the democratic charter. In hindsight,
then, it would appear that Maritain may have underestimated the
potential divisive power of the diverse theoretical commitments that lay
dormant in that apparent "unity of moral consciousness" that
had its apotheosis after the Great War.
III. The Neutral Faith the Neutralizes Faith
The second problem with the attempt to ground politics on nothing but a
practical, secular consensus is the tendency for that consensus to
undermine the priority, in first public and then private life, of
supernatural or spiritual reality, and even to invert the proper
subordination of the mundane to the spiritual. I contend that such a
"neutral" consensus brings about a transformation of the
religious convictions of its citizens from publicly relevant, supremely
important guides for thought and action, into mere private bulwarks for
the "more important" public values of the democratic faith. Since the
democratic charter, representing the sole blueprint for the production
and maintenance of the public good, rests upon no particular
philosophical or religious creed (though it, as Maritain insists, is a
product of the Gospel and can not exist without its continued
inspiration) and, in fact, retains its integrity and strength precisely
because it eschews a metaphysical and religious foundation, then it
would follow, I would maintain, that religiously-relevant political
prescriptions would be rendered inane at best, and dangerous at worst,
in the hearts and minds of the citizenry. Active participation in such
an order would tend to habituate one into privatizing his truth claims,
first in public but then in private, such that religious indifferentism
or apathy would be result. The enforced divorce of one’s deep,
comprehensive worldview from political life, inasmuch as one is
"told" in countless ways (education, media, law, church
sermons!) that such a divorce is morally obligatory by the exigencies of
pluralism, would tend to make a rigorous, politically relevant Catholic
doctrine like the social reign of Christ the King seem obsolete—or
even heretical!
The reason why "neutrality" ends up enforcing a certain
dogma is because no publicly enforced policy can ever be neutral towards
religion. The ostensibly pragmatic concession to religious pluralism has
served, in the liberal regimes of our day, to mask the institution of a
hidden religion:
For since the liberal state must act, and since it cannot take any
religious prescriptions as authoritative for its actions, the liberal
state in principle denies that there are any true politically relevant
religious prescriptions. Liberalism rests on a theological
premise."
The irony is that the proposal of the so-called religiously-neutral
state as the only way to deal with deep pluralism itself establishes a
religion and a set of values. This is the religion of liberalism."
As it is impossible for one to serve both God and mammon, what would
happen to a religious believer who attempts to serve a democratic faith
that requires the sacrifice of the public, temporal significance of his
religious faith? It would be perfectly natural for him to interpret his
obligatory devotion to the publicly celebrated, legally enforced, and
socially respectable democratic faith as less important than his
voluntary devotion to his publicly neglected, legally ignored, and
socially eschewed religious faith. The consequence of prolonged
habituation in such a regime is obvious. It is not possible, without a
heroic amount of grace, effort and vigilance, to hold both the
"theologically-neutral" theological premise of the democratic
charter and the theologically charged premises of a Christian political
theology. For this reason we should be very hesitant to accept the
purported neutrality of even Maritain’s Christ-inspired democratic
charter. Maritain, of course, would never had wanted any part of such a
trivialization of Christian belief—on the contrary, he explicitly
called for a new Christendom! But one mustn’t ignore the possibility
that he may have promoted this very obsoletion when he denied the need
for truth as a basis for social order in the modern world:
Hence we must renounce the search for a common profession of faith,
whether it be the medieval one of the Apostle’s Creed, or the natural
religion of Leibniz, or the positive philosophy of Auguste Comte, or
that minimum of Kantian morality invoked in France by the first
theorists of Laicism: we must give up seeking in a common profession of
faith the source and principle of unity in the social body.
The Hungarian-born Aurel Kolnai, an outstanding but unfortunately
underappreciated political philosopher of the twentieth century, in a
savagely critical review of Maritain’s Man and the State wrote
this: "In the upshot, what we are faced with here is not Christ
recognizing the autonomy, in his own rightful domain, of Caesar; rather
it is Anti-Christ begged to accord an asylum to Christ." Though I
am convinced that Maritain would have rather died than betray Christ, we
must ask if a conceptual betrayal, at least, could not have been the
unintended consequence of his thought on this matter.
IV. A State of Grace—Without Grace?
Maritain explicitly stated that the one condition that would make or
break the success of the democratic charter was a widespread reverence
for spiritual goods. The question we must ask is how Maritain could have
expected non-Catholics and especially non-Christians, that is, those
either partially or fully separated from the font of grace, without
which all true virtue, both natural and supernatural, is impossible, to
revere the societal values of the Gospel adequate to the attainment of a
genuine temporal peace? Contrast Maritain’s optimism to these passages
by Pius XI and Leo XIII, the former who wrote these words from
Quas Primas very near to the time when Maritain wrote his
Integral Humanism:
We referred to the chief causes of the difficulties under
which mankind was laboring. And We remember saying that these manifold
evils in the world were due to the fact that the majority of men had
thrust Jesus Christ and his holy law out of their lives; that these had
no place either in private affairs or in politics: and we said further,
that as long as individuals and states refused to submit to the rule of
our Savior, there would be no really hopeful prospect of a lasting peace
among nations.
The Church of Christ is the true and sole teacher of virtue and
guardian of morals. She it is who preserves in their purity the
principles from which duties flow, and by setting forth most urgent
reasons for virtuous life, bids us not only to turn away from wicked
deeds, but even to curb all movements of the mind that are opposed to
reason, even though they be not carried out in action.
Whence came Maritain’s optimism for a religiously-neutral
public charter in light of these sober Papal admonitions to explicit and
formal societal and political submission to Christ? Perhaps a clue can
be found in this passage of Maritain’s:
Thus there is a sort of vegetative development and growth,
so to speak, of moral knowledge and moral feeling, which is in itself
independent of the philosophical systems, . . . As a result these
various systems, while disputing about the "why," prescribe in
their practical conclusions rules of behavior which appear on the whole
as almost the same for any given period and culture [my italics].
We clearly see here Maritain’s belief in the inevitability
of moral progress, even in the absence of philosophical or religious
progress in truth. Now, Maritain did hold that the sole reason for the
evident moral progress of modern man was the Gospel’s influence;
however, for Maritain such progress does not require explicit belief and
submission to the Gospel’s truths and precepts on the part of individual
men. In short, it is not necessary for the individual to explicitly
accept or live the Gospel in order for him to accept and live the
Gospel-inspired democratic charter. Maritain appeared to believe that
simply by living in the modern historical era, an era now thoroughly
pervaded by the temporal spirit of the Gospel (at least, in the West),
one would become Christian enough in spirit, if not in confession, to
uphold a social order authentically Christian.
Here is the main problem with this: Since the goods of the democratic
charter are based upon the natural moral law, as Maritain maintains, and
since abiding in the light of the Church’s infallible interpretation and
elucidation of the natural law is not a requirement of either
subscription to or action in accord with this charter, as Maritain also
maintains, it would follow that the level of understanding of the
natural moral goods in the democratic charter by the non-Catholic
subscribers would be, at best, imperfect. Why, then, would Maritain have
advocated such an imperfect state of affairs as an ideal for which
Catholics should strive?
The Church herself teaches that men cannot adequately understand
in theory, let alone fulfill in practice, the natural law without the
help of its author, God, and its divinely appointed interpreter, the
Roman Catholic Church. Here are two quotes expressing this truth, one
the official teaching of the Church on Ecclesial public law as expressed
by a scholar in 1951 (the exact date of the publication of Man and
the State) the other, a passage by Ward irrefutable in its logic:
The only true doctrine is that civil society cannot prescind
from the ultimate end, both because the temporal welfare implies an
ordering to the spiritual and supernatural, and because the individual
citizens are directly and positively bound to tend to it."
The Church professes to be infallible in her teaching of morals no
less than of faith. If, then, Catholicism be true, and if Catholics have
the fullest ground for knowing it to be true, the one healthy,
desirable, and legitimate state of civil society is that the Church’s
doctrines, principles, and laws should be recognized without question as
its one basis of legislation and administration; and that the civil
ruler, in all his highest and most admirable functions should be
profoundly submissive to the Church’s authority.
Of course, Maritain’s whole point was that even a
completely distorted understanding of the natural law is no obstacle
towards the success of the democratic charter, provided that in spite of
intellectual errors its subscribers revere the
values of the charter, i.e., truth, love, human persons, etc. I
reiterate here the oft-repeated truth of John Paul II that the
revelation of Jesus Christ is the only mirror in which man can fully
contemplate and comprehend himself. Is reverence for the human person
and the practice of brotherly love, then, really attainable without the
belief in Jesus Christ, Who was the very incarnation of personhood and
love itself? Is even political peace possible without spiritual rebirth
through Baptism and the infusion of sanctifying grace that comes via the
Church’s sacraments? In short, can man by the unaided exercise of his
natural powers attain his natural end, in which a genuinely good
political order is indispensable, through faith in a mere democratic
charter?
Although Maritain knew that man could not attain his natural end
perfectly without grace, as his mentor St. Thomas taught
him—"But in the state of corrupt nature, man falls short of what
he could do by his nature, so that he is unable to fulfill it by his own
natural powers"—he did appear to imply, however, that reverence
and brotherly love for our neighbor, as well as a robust devotion to
moral truth, could be attained without God’s direct help. This is
problematic; for, insomuch as man is unable to fulfill his natural
perfection without the aid of grace, and insofar as man’s natural
perfection is both a constitutive element and product of political life,
we can not expect anything but a very imperfect—if not downright
evil— social order without the direct influence of sanctifying grace
on the individual level. In short, the kind of reverence for natural
goods that the democratic charter requires is only to be found rarely
and fleetingly (perhaps only in times of suffering and war, such as we
experienced in the aftermath of both World War II and 9/11) among fallen
and unredeemed men. Perhaps this reverence was pervasive among European
and American men after the trauma of World War II, but the evidence is
now in of its quick dissipation. Such reverence, I would argue, can only
be preserved under the social reign of Jesus Christ, not the reign of
"democratic values."
V. Discerning the Spirits: Christ or Chaos?
I admit the possibility that my analysis of Maritain’s political
thought may be entirely off-base. I say this sincerely, in spite of the
confident tone of my criticisms, because in many ways I have simplified
the thinking of Maritain to make my criticism of him easier—he is an
incredibly complex thinker whose ideas resist simplification. I have
left out many of his statements that would seem to refute my
characterization of him as a kind of proto-Rawlsian liberal; to wit:
"Well, those Christians who are turned toward the future and who
hope—be it a long range hope—for a new Christendom, a new
Christianly inspired civilization, know that ‘the world has done with
neutrality. Willingly or unwillingly, States will be obliged to make a
choice for or against the Gospel’." "The world cannot be
neutral with respect to the kingdom of God. Either it is vivified by it,
or it struggles against it." "Woe to the world if the
Christian were to isolate and separate his temporal mission (then it
would be wind only) from his spiritual vocation!"
But the very juxtaposition of two seemingly contradictory sentiments
coming from the same man suggests the accuracy of my thesis: I see it as
the tell-tale sign of the distortion of theological and philosophical
principle that can result from a failure to "discern the
spirits." In some of his writings, Maritain issues a clear
clarion-call for Catholics to work for the social reign of Christ the
King; in others, he demands that Catholics uphold a religiously-neutral
democratic charter. On the one hand, Maritain declares the fact of
religious division to be "unfortunate," and the freedom of
citizens to practice false religions an evil to be tolerated "in
order to avoid greater evils," on the other, he declares the
superiority of a new Christendom built precisely on an
unregenerate religious pluralism! Glenn Olsen gives us an insight into a
possible cause of Maritain’s confusion:
I have suggested that indiscriminate praise of pluralism is a
disservice to life in society, and that Americans who constantly try to
make virtues out of the necessities stemming from their sectarian
origins, have failed to achieve any measured understanding of all the
issues involved in the question of pluralism."
I hope I have succeeded in attaining both a "measured
understanding" of at least some of the important issues involved in
the question of pluralism, and of Maritain’s ideas on the question as
well. Maritain’s "blind spot" to the imminent dangers of
pluralism was shared by many Catholic intellectuals in the immediate
post-war period, and no doubt this writer would have shared in the
blindness also. However, such a blind spot can not be excused today, in
the clear light of those evils that now beset our country, evils whose
existence Maritain had no way to predict. Insofar as America was, for
Maritain, a veritable incarnation of the democratic faith in the modern
day, and insofar as we have determined that that faith is flawed, I
think it can now be admitted that Maritain made a grave error in his
discernment of the American spirit of his day. The American spirit, in
spite of its original goodness, has now been taken over by evil forces,
forces that can not be exorcised by anything other than an
unadulterated, vigorous, politically-relevant faith in Jesus Christ and
the Church that He founded, a Church that must be, for the sake of both
the Church’s honor and the temporal common good, the publicly recognized
guide for men in both individual and social life. And for the latter to
occur, we need to work for a nationwide conversion to the Catholic
faith. If the democratic faith was a conduit for good in the days when
the American spirit was still vitally Christian, it is a conduit for
evil in our day when abortion has become a secular "blessed
sacrament," homosexuality a new-age "spiritual counsel,"
and the prayer, "They shall be created, and thou shall renew the
face of the earth," co-opted in a new Pentecost of human cloning.
We close with the wise words of William Ward, whose accurate discernment
of the spirit of his day we must imitate in order to save ours:
Towards the prevailing national spirit, on the contrary, our
only reasonable attitude is one of deep jealously and suspicion; because
it is charged with principles which, for the corruption of human nature,
are sure to be more false than true, and from which we should keep
ourselves entirely free, until we have measured them by their only true
standard, the Church’s voice.
Copyright 2002 Thaddeus J. Kozinsky
|